Naar aanleiding van het optreden van Paul Cliteur in het Wilders II-proces rijst de vraag hoe de inzet van een rechtsgang zich verhoudt tot de eigen aard van de filosofie. Aan de ene kant vertolkt filosofie precies dat register van waarheid dat in het recht aan de orde is. Aan de andere kant is die vertolking zo oneindig open dat ze strijdt met het gesloten karakter van het recht als een proces dat conflicten moet beëindigen door gezagvolle beslissingen. Socrates’ optreden in zijn eigen proces toont aan: de slechtste dienst die de filosofie het recht kan bewijzen, is het verlengstuk te worden van het positieve recht en zich bij voorbaat beschikbaar te stellen als een vindplaats van argumenten wanneer de juridische argumenten op zijn. De slotparagraaf argumenteert dat Cliteur deze socratische les terzijde legt. Als gevolg daarvan geeft hij een geforceerde lezing van het Felter-arrest en mist hij de kern van het begrip ‘onverdraagzaamheid’. |
Search result: 20 articles
Discussion |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2020 |
Authors | Klaas Rozemond |
Author's information |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2020 |
Authors | Klaas Rozemond |
Author's information |
Editorial |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2017 |
Authors | Anne Ruth Mackor, Jeroen ten Voorde and Pauline Westerman |
Author's information |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2017 |
Keywords | rechtsfilosofie, politiek proces, onverdraagzaamheid, Wilders II |
Authors | Bert van Roermund |
AbstractAuthor's information |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2017 |
Keywords | Klaas Rozemond, Ronald M. Dworkin, Legality in criminal law, Rights conception of the rule of law, Legal certainty |
Authors | Briain Jansen |
AbstractAuthor's information |
The extensive interpretation of criminal law to the detriment of the defendant in criminal law is often problematized in doctrinal theory. Extensive interpretation is then argued to be problematic in the light of important ideals such as democracy and legal certainty in criminal law. In the Dutch discussion of this issue, Klaas Rozemond has argued that sometimes extensive interpretation is mandated by the rule of law in order to protect the rights of victims. Rozemond grounds his argument on a reading of Dworkin’s distinction between the rule-book and the rights conception of the rule of law. In this article, I argue that Dworkin’s rights conception, properly considered, does not necessarily mandate the imposition of criminal law or its extensive interpretation in court in order to protect victims’ rights. |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2015 |
Keywords | international criminal law, judicial reasoning, casuistry, genocide |
Authors | Marjolein Cupido |
AbstractAuthor's information |
International criminal courts have made an important contribution to the development of international criminal law. Through case law, the courts have fine-tuned and modernized outdated concepts of international crimes and liability theories. In studying this practice, scholars have so far focused on the judicial interpretation of statutory and customary rules, thereby paying little attention to the rules’ application in individual cases. In this article, I reveal the limitations of this approach and illustrate how insights from casuistry can advance international criminal law discourse. In particular, I use the example of genocide to show that casuistic case law analyses can help scholars clarify the meaning of the law and appraise the application of substantive legal concepts in individual cases. Based on these observations, I argue that scholars should complement their current research with studies into the casuistry of international criminal law. |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2013 |
Keywords | homo faber, homo agens, human condition, participatory judgment, law-linked justice, existence-linked justice |
Authors | Peter van Schilfgaarde |
AbstractAuthor's information |
This paper concentrates on the dynamic tension between law as it is ‘made’ by legal professionals, functioning as homo faber, and law as it is experienced by citizens, functioning as homo agens. In between those two worlds, law develops as a human condition, a term borrowed from Hannah Arendt. It is argued that, in regard to law development and administration of justice, the function of homo agens should have priority over the function of homo faber. The two basic faculties that connect the two worlds are judgment and speech. This leads to further thoughts on the character of judgment as ‘participatory judgment,’ the function of ‘middle terms’ in legal language and the concept of ‘shared responsibility.’ |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2012 |
Keywords | banality of evil, Hannah Arendt, Adolf Eichmann, Holocaust studies, philosophy of international criminal law |
Authors | Klaas Rozemond |
AbstractAuthor's information |
In her book Eichmann in Jerusalem Hannah Arendt concluded that the Eichmann trial taught us the lesson of the ‘fearsome, word-and-thought-defying banality of evil’. Arendt explained the concept of banality as thoughtlessness: Eichmann did not realize what he was doing when he planned and executed the Final Solution of the Jewish Question in Nazi Germany. In this article Arendt’s analysis of Eichmann’s evil is criticized from an internal perspective: the conclusion that Eichmann was thoughtless cannot be founded on the information Arendt herself gives, especially her reports on Eichmann’s idealism, his knowledge of Kant’s categorical imperative, his Pontius Pilate feeling during the Wannsee Conference, and the two crises of conscience Eichmann experienced during the Holocaust. This information shows that Eichmann clearly realized what he was doing in a moral sense and consciously decided to go on with the Final Solution on the basis of his own convictions as a Nazi. |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2010 |
Keywords | Beccaria, criminal law, nodal governance, social contract |
Authors | Klaas Rozemond |
AbstractAuthor's information |
Les Johnston and Clifford Shearing argue in their book, Governing Security, that the state has lost its monopoly on the governance of security. Private security arrangements have formed a networked governance of security in which the criminal law of the state is just one of the many knots or ‘nodes’ of the security network. Johnston and Shearing consider On Crimes and Punishment, written by Cesare Beccaria in the 18th century, as the most important statement of the classical security program which has withered away in the networked governance of the risk society. This article critizes the way Johnston and Shearing analyze Beccaria’s social contract theory and it formulates a Beccarian theory of the criminal law and nodal governance which explains the causes of crime and the rise of nodal governance and defends the central role of the state in anchoring security arrangements based on private contracts and property rights. |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2010 |
Keywords | Legitimation durch Verfahren, criminal law, expert-witnesses, truth, reliability of evidence |
Authors | Anne Ruth Mackor |
AbstractAuthor's information |
Huls has argued that the idea that judges are truth-finders is misleading. In the first part of the paper I put his claim to the test. Against Huls I argue that the aim of procedures in criminal lawsuits is not only to guarantee binding decisions but also to help to find the truth. In the second part of the paper I investigate the role expert-witnesses play in truth-finding. Cleiren and Loth have argued that experts fail to understand the differences between legal and scientific ways of truth-finding. It turns out that Cleiren does not offer an argument for her claim and that Loth’s claim fails too, since it confuses coherence as truth and coherence as epistemic justification. I conclude that legal scholars, rather than experts, fail to understand the nature of legal and scientific truth-finding. |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2010 |
Keywords | psychology of law, criminal law, miscarriages of justice, hypothetical reasoning |
Authors | Klaas Rozemond |
AbstractAuthor's information |
In their book De slapende rechter (The sleeping judge) Dutch legal psychologists W.A. Wagenaar, H. Israëls and P.J. van Koppen claim that Dutch judges wrongfully convict suspects in certain cases because these judges generally fail to understand the way hypothetical reasoning works in relation to empirical evidence. This article argues that Wagenaar, Israëls and Van Koppen are basically right in their claim that reasoning on evidence in criminal cases should have the form of hypothetical reasoning. However, they fail to apply this form of reasoning to their own analysis of Dutch criminal cases and the causes of wrongful convictions. Therefore, their conclusion that a form of revision of convictions outside of the criminal law system should be introduced does not meet their own methodological standards. |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2008 |
Keywords | bemiddeling, delinquent, slachtoffer, strafrecht, identiteitsbewijs, strafvordering, verzoening, aansprakelijkheid, bemiddelaar, confrontatie |
Authors | K. Rozemond |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2006 |
Keywords | verdrag, referendum, democratie, lidstaat, noodzakelijkheid, verlies, Europese unie, identiteit, pleidooi, idee |
Authors | T. Mertens |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2006 |
Keywords | rechtspraak, burgerlijk recht, motivering, mediation, wetgeving, gedetineerde, onderwijs, aansprakelijkheid, ambtenaar, arbiter |
Authors | R.A. Khan and K. Rozemond |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2005 |
Keywords | moord, rechtsstaat, strafrecht, wetgeving, geweld, politie, pleidooi, misdrijf, motivering, opzet |
Authors | K. Rozemond |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 1 2005 |
Authors | K. Rozemond |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2004 |
Keywords | Europees hof voor de rechten van de mens, verdrag, model, pleidooi, rechtspraak, citaat, diefstal, goede zeden, homoseksualiteit, lidstaat |
Authors | A. Soeteman |
Book Review |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2004 |
Keywords | auteur, autonomie, democratie, dwaling, kwaliteit, leerling, levering, overlijden, prestatie, uitleg |
Authors | A.J. Wolthuis |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2002 |
Keywords | strafbaar feit, minister van justitie, openbaar ministerie, aansprakelijkheid, staat der nederlanden, strafbaarheid, strafrechtelijke aansprakelijkheid, algemeen belang, gemeente, opschorting |
Authors | N. Rozemond |
Article |
|
Journal | Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, Issue 2 2002 |
Keywords | strafrechter, strafrecht, misdrijf, kwaliteit, verkrachting, huwelijk, auteur, uitleg, voorwaarde, verbod |
Authors | E. Claes |